57 pages • 1 hour read
A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Prefaces and Introduction
Part I: “Transcendental Aesthetic”
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book I, Chapter I
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book I, Chapter II
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book II, Chapters I-II
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Book II, Chapter III
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Division II, Books I-II, Chapter I
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Division II, Book II, Chapter II
Part II: “Transcendental Logic,” Division II, Book II, Chapter III
Transcendental Doctrine of the Method
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Further Reading & Resources
Tools
In the previous chapter of the transcendental analytic Kant presented the pure forms of understanding through the table of judgements and the table of categories. In this chapter, he must show how it can be that these forms can actually be applied to objects of experience. He refers to this project as transcendental deduction, that is, an explanation of the necessary way in which concepts are integral to the presentation of objects in human experience.
For Kant, experience is constituted by two very different elements: matter and form. Matter is provided to the mind through the receptive faculty of sensibility and form is applied to the matter “from the inner source of pure intuition and thought,” i.e., understanding. Though we have investigated both sensibility and understanding, we as yet have no idea how these two can be combined to create experience. Kant stresses the importance of discovering and deducing the source of this combination (synthesis). The problem is a difficult one: “how subjective conditions of thought could have objective validity, i.e., how they could yield conditions for the possibility of all cognitions of objects” (145). Guaranteeing objectivity requires nothing less than universal and necessary application, hence deduction.
The 12 categories of understanding have objective validity because it is only through them that objects of experience are possible. Kant discusses sense, imagination, and apperception as the three necessary transcendental powers of the mind for all experience. Each of these corresponds to a specific synthesis that is required for experience: the synthesis of apprehension (in sensibility), the synthesis of reproduction (in imagination), and the synthesis of recognition (in the concepts of the understanding). Each of these is necessary for understanding and understanding is in turn necessary for experience.
Kant then discusses each of these syntheses in turn. In apprehension, the stuff of the world is united in a single coherent intuition combining the senses of space and time. In reproduction, the imagination reproduces these appearances. In the synthesis of recognition, the unity of consciousness recognizes the concept of the object. Kant calls this fundamental and unified consciousness “transcendental apperception” (159). He writes, “the numerical unity of this apperception lies a priori at the basis of all concepts” (159). The identity of an individual’s consciousness makes all concepts of objects possible.
Note: In the first edition of the Critique (1781), Kant wrote a third section to the “Deduction of the Pure Concepts of Understanding.” In the second edition (1787) he replaced this with a rewritten second edition.
In Section III of the first edition Kant expands on the idea of the unity of apperception. He makes a distinction between the productive and reproductive imagination. The productive imagination is responsible for the transcendental unity of apperception, which is prior to all experience and a condition of experience, while the reproductive imagination acts based on experience. The imagination makes an image out of the manifold intuited by our sense of space and time. This is an “active power” that grounds experience. There are experiences of consciousness in empirical reality. They are united as a single consciousness through the act of apperception, the transcendental condition. Kant calls this the “constant and enduring I” (170). Kant writes that the faculty of understanding can also be formed as the capacity to form rules.
In Section II of the second edition Kant provides a more detailed attempt to explain the transcendental unity of apperception. He introduces the problem of combination and describes it as the “presentation of the synthetic unity of the manifold” (176). Kant is driven to clarify how this combination is possible, and transcendental apperception is the most fundamental answer to that question. This apperception is the “highest point” of the understanding, and the understanding, through judgment and categorization is the power of combination. The transcendental unity of apperception is objective because it is the condition for the concept of an object. It can also be called transcendental self-consciousness. Empirical consciousness is merely subjective. Kant discusses the relationship between inner sense, imagination, and understanding. Although personal existence is guaranteed through transcendental apperception, this personal existence can only be presented in time through inner sense. Therefore, our cognitions of ourselves are not anything more than momentary appearances of the self in time and not direct cognitions of ourselves.
“The Deduction of the Pure Concepts of Understanding” is some of the most mind-bending material in modern philosophy. Kant was aware of his reader’s potential confusion: “Such obscurity is unavoidable as one begins to walk along a path that has never been walked upon before” (153). Kant’s task in this book is to determine the limits of experience. Among other things, this entails comprehension of how conscious experience is possible at all. Thus far, Kant has already identified sensibility and understanding as the two faculties of the human mind necessary for experience and has outlined the basic nature of both. Now he must show how they can be combined to present a unified world of appearances.
To do this, this he must introduce the idea of the imagination, which brings the world of intuition in sensibility to an image presented before consciousness, and, more fundamentally, the transcendental unity of apperception. The latter is the idea of a self, a conscious I, that accompanies and unifies all experience. Without this act of unification there is nothing to bind experiences together. Kant writes, “Hence the original and necessary consciousness of one’s own identity is at the same time a consciousness of an equally necessary unity of the synthesis of all appearances according to concepts” (159). In other words, self-consciousness is that which brings all subsequent acts of understanding, which acts through categorization and judgment, under one fully realized umbrella.
At the time, this was a novel idea. In the 17th-18th centuries there were serious debates regarding the nature of personal identity, including David Hume’s skeptical denial of the reality of personal identity. By making personal identity the defining condition for the possibility of experience, Kant overcomes the problems of identity articulated by Hume. Kant takes this as a ground of all cognition: “And thus the synthetic unity of apperception is the highest point, to which we must attach all use of the understanding, even the whole of logic, and in accordance with it transcendental philosophy” (178).
One of the intriguing elements of Kant’s transcendental idealism is the fact that his work is concerned primarily with the “subjective sources of cognition,” of which there are three: sense, imagination, and apperception. This does not mean that there are not also objective sources of cognition. This objective source is the transcendental object, i.e., the object as it is independent of our experience of it. However, since we cannot know anything about the object as it is independent of our subjective cognition, there is nothing to say about it. It is unknowable. All we can hope to truly know is the subjective side of the story. Despite this, Kant still wants to uncover the ways in which the subjective sources of cognition have objective validity. Transcendental conditions are necessary and universal, so although they are subjectively sourced, they should apply objectively to all possible experiences.
Plus, gain access to 8,800+ more expert-written Study Guides.
Including features:
By Immanuel Kant